Perhaps
the place where Plato/Socrates is the most pragmatic in The Apology, and by most,
I mean the place where he is philosophically pragmatic is during the sentencing
phase.
Socrates
has been convicted, but no penalty has been exacted. Meletus, his accuser, asks
for death. Socrates is then asked to suggest a punishment he deems suitable.
After musing about several alternatives, one of the most satirical passages in
all the dialogues, Socrates weighs them against death and asks, “When I do not
know whether death is a good or an evil, why should I propose a
penalty which would certainly be an evil?” About as pragmatic a question as one
could ask—at least philosophically.
Philosophically, according
to James “The pragmatic method is
primarily a method of settling metaphysical disputes that otherwise might be
interminable” (Pragmatism 25). What
is the question Socrates just asked but interminable, that is, unanswerable?
After he has been condemned, Socrates riffs on death at length:
“Let us
reflect in another way, and we shall see that there is great reason
to hope that death is a good, for one of two things: - either death is a state of nothingness and utter unconsciousness, or, as men
say, there is a change and migration of the soul from this
world to another. Now if you suppose that there is no
consciousness, but a sleep like the sleep of him who is
undisturbed even by the sight of dreams, death will be an unspeakable
gain. For if a person were to select the night in which his sleep
was undisturbed even by dreams, and were to compare with this the other
days and nights of his life, and then were to tell us how many days and nights he had passed in the course of his life better and more
pleasantly than this one, I think that any man, I will not say
a private man, but even the great king, will not find many such
days or nights, when compared with the others.”
This passage
sounds like James’s well known metaphor about the squirrel and the tree. (A man
is on one side of a tree; a squirrel on the other. As the man tries to go round
the tree to see the squirrel, does he go “round the squirrel or
not?” (Pragmatism 25). James’s answer is
to long for a blog. We’ll just summarize him by paraphrasing his take on the pragmatic
method: It’s the same whether the man goes around the squirrel or the squirrel
goes around the man. So, why worry about it.
Though I self-identify
as a pragmatist, I find James’s stance troubling, since I am prone to tell
students in advanced writing or theory classes that the only questions that
really interest me are the ones that
don’t have an answer, that are, in fact, interminable.
Socrates’s musing about
death help me see that those unending questions, while unanswerable, are not
metaphysical but pragmatic, because as Socrates realized, they govern how we
act. Had he feared death, he would have acted much differently in The Apology than he did. Something he
himself points out.
Those interminable
questions are about what Socrates referred to as “virtue” and virtue affects
us every day at the street level.
No comments:
Post a Comment