In this brief chapter Quintilian categorizes arts as 1) those concerted with knowledge, theoretikē, or contemplative arts, the primary goals of which is study; his example: astronomy; 2) The active arts, praktikē, those arts that are more concerned with the immediate experience than producing something, such as dance or theater; 3) and the productive arts, poetikē, such as painting, which are concerned with the creation of an object that exists after the creative moment.
We immediately recognize that each art may have attributes of the other. Quintilian did as well, claiming that rhetoric had attributes of all three:
"for the subject of it may sometimes be restricted to contemplation,
since there will be oratory in an orator even though he be silent . . . There is some enjoyment, and perhaps the greatest of all enjoyments, in
retired meditation, and the pleasure derived from knowledge is pure when
it is withdrawn from action . . . But oratory will also effect
something similar to a productive art in written speeches and
historical compositions . . . Yet if it must be classed as one of the three sorts
of arts which I have mentioned, let it, as its performance consists
chiefly in the mere act and as it is most frequently exhibited in act,
be called an active or a practical art, for the one term is of the same
signification as the other."
http://rhetoric.eserver.org/quintilian/2/chapter18.html
Posts about running, trail running, listening to Plato instead of music while running.
Friday, April 29, 2016
Saturday, April 23, 2016
Institutes Book 2 Chapter 17 Quntilian's Defense of Rhetoric (Cont.)
It’s not clear whether
Quintilian is directly answering Plato or simply a tradition of thought that
follows from Plato. Here he answers Plato’s argument that the rhetor must know
all things he speaks of. Instead, Quintilian makes the post-structuralist
argument, than none of us can ever be certain.
“Oratory is the art of speaking well, and the orator knows
how to speak well. But it is said he does not know whether
what he says is true; neither do the philosophers, who say that fire, or water,
or the four elements, or indivisible atoms are the principles from which all
things had their origin, know that what they say is true; nor do those who
calculate the distances of the stars, and the magnitudes of the sun and the
earth, yet every one of them calls his system an art.”
Institutes Book 2 Chapter 16 Quntilian's Defense of Rhetoric
In Book Two, Chapters
16 through 20, Quintilian defends rhetoric against all comers. First, he takes
on Plato’s complaint that rhetoric can be used as easily for ill as for good
with a bit of satire.
“In the hands of physicians poisons have been found, and
among those who abuse the name of philosophers have been occasionally detected
the most horrible crimes. We must reject food, for it has often given rise to
ill health; we must never go under roofs, for they sometimes fall upon those
who dwell beneath them; a sword must not be forged for a soldier, for a robber
may use the same weapon.”
His deeper argument,
however, is to question the definition of rhetoric as persuasion, redefining it
is eloquence. Though this sets him up for Ramus’s attack later, it allows him
to connect rhetoric to virtue.
"But these points may perhaps be left to the consideration of
those who think that the substance of eloquence lies in the power to persuade.
But if eloquence be the art of speaking well (the definition which I adopt), so
that a true orator must be, above all, a good man, it must assuredly be acknowledged
that it is a useful art."
As yet, Quintilian hasn’t
explained why it requires a good man to be a rhetorician, other than the “true”
rhetoric argument. But, that’s what Weaver argues Plato is actually arguing in “Phaedrus.”
Wednesday, April 20, 2016
The Seeds of Vico and Grassi
In this brief statement, Quintilian places the imaginative above the analytical, or at least before the analytical, a theme that is repeated and elaborated on in Vico and Grassi. At question in Quintilian is whether the imaginative is elementary or the foundational. If elementary it can be left behind when analysis comes to the fore; if foundational provides much of the framework for invention.
"Exuberance
is easilv remedied, but barrenness is incurable, be your efforts what they may.
To my mind the boy who gives least promise is one in whom the critical faculty
develops in advance of the imagination. I like to see the first fruits of the
mind copious to excess and almost extravagant in their profusion."
Book II, Chapter 4
Book II, Chapter 4
Sunday, April 17, 2016
Quintilian Institutes: Verisimilitude and Narrative
At the beginning of Book II, Quintilian categorizes narrative
verisimilitude according to the categories "fictitious" and "true."
Later he questions the "truth" in some historical narratives,
even though he classifies them as true here. It's going to be
interesting to see how his different categories play out when he
get to the "best method of narration" later. Will he, like
Corax and Tisias play truth games with the probable and make
the worse the better?
"Now there are three forms of narrative, without 2 counting the type used in actual legal cases. First there is the fictitious narrative as we get it in tragedies and poems, which is not merely not true but has little resemblance to truth. Secondly, there is the realistic narrative as presented by comedies, which, though not true, has yet a certain verisimili- tude. Thirdly there is the historical narrative, which is an exposition of actual fact. Poetic narratives are the property of the teacher of literature. The rhetorician therefore should begin with the his- torical narrative, whose force is in proportion to its truth.I will, however, postpone my demonstration 3 of what I regard as the best method of narration till I come to deal with narration as required in the courts."
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)