Tuesday, April 12, 2016

Quintilian, The Institutes of Oratory, Proper Usage



In chapters five and six of Book I, Quintilian carefully maps out proper usage, drawing on analogy, etymology, and rational arguments to establish the proper usage. These chapters are reminiscent of Socrates’s review of the origins of names and their true meanings in Cratylus

Though I found most of Cratylus pedantic, I can easily imagine Plato’s audience listening to these passages being read with interest, perhaps even laughter. After all, Plato often included in-jokes in his dialogues, and modern readers are not part of the "in" crowd. They'd fly right over our heads. 

Unlike Quintilian, for whom the litany of proper usage seems sufficient to his task, the education of the young, Plato ends his long list with an explanation of how knowing the proper names can be used in dialectic to trip up an opponent, thus revealing his own method of deconstruction as well as complicating his theory of language. Language is referential, yes, but it refers to what I can convince you it refers to.  

Quintilian ends these chapters by drawing an analogy between “common usage” as a means of deciding on whether a specific word or phrase is acceptable, and “common usage” to decide moral issues. If it's not a good idea for one, it's not a good idea for the other.

He doesn’t go as far as Plato in condemning democracy. Instead, he argues that the common usage of learned men should take precedence over the common usage of the masses, on the surface as elitist an outlook as Plato’s. However, I think we have to be careful when we play the “elitist” card. As soon as I thought "elitist" while listening to The Institutes of Oratory, I reminded myself that for elite Roman citizens, learned men often meant the Greek slaves who tutored their sons, and intriguing convolution of class, ethnicity, and education. (The most elitist language in that sentence refers to gender, doesn’t it?

No comments:

Post a Comment